Spaces
02 Sep 2021 - Tags: analysis-qual-prep
On to day Yesterday Tuesday1 was all about measures
and integrable functions. Today, then, let’s talk about spaces of integrable
functions. It’s time for
Thankfully, this should be a comparatively short post, since
The lower values of
Conversely, large values of
As an example, think of
This has a singularity at
Conversely, consider the constant
This function doesn’t decay at all, so is certainly not
A less silly example might be
This function decays too slowly to be
The most important cases are
To start, let’s remind ourselves what
As is often the case, we need to treat
Now we can define (for
As usual, we will consider two functions the same if they agree
almost everywhere. We will also often write
It turns out
Let’s see some important examples of
-
If
is the lebesgue measure on , then is one of the most common examples used in practice. This forms the basis for a lot of intuition about spaces. -
Sometimes
is too big. We might think of working with . Common choices are and . -
Another important example is the circle
. The space is the archetypal first example for fourier theory5. -
An example in a different vein is
with the counting measure. This is often called . Here our functions can be thought of as sequences of complex numbers, which makes this a particularly appealing setting for small examples. We’ll find extremely useful when we talk about hilbert spaces. -
The counterpoint to example (3) is
, again with the counting measure. These are bi-infinite sequences of complex numbers, often written , and these will be related to functions on the circle by means of the fourier transform.
One of the most important tools we have for proving properties about
These sets of functions are dense in
-
Simple Functions (with finite-measure support). That is, functions of the form
. These are dense almost by definition6 and form the base for proving other, more exiting density results. After all, to show a class of functions is dense in , it suffices to show it can approximate the simple functions. If we allow infinite measure support, then these functions are dense in as well. -
Continuous Functions (with compact support). Obviously these are great. We don’t always need the extra power of compact support, but it’s good to know it’s there!
These families of dense functions require a notion of differentiation.
They’re definitely true in
-
Smooth Functions (with compact support). We love differentiation in this household.
-
Schwarz Functions. As long as we’re discussing things that only work in
, these are functions which are not only smooth, but which vanish more quickly than any polynomial, and all their derivatives vanish that quickly too. We’ll talk more about these in the post about fourier theory.
These families of functions also require some compactness condition (because we’re using the stone-weierstrass theorem).
-
Polynomials. On
, we can approximate by polynomials -
Polynomials in
. On , we can approximate by “trigonometric polynomials”. This will be extremely important when we start talking about fourier theory.
There’s actually a kind of master theorem for density results in
Before we move on, these density results are one potential source of
motivation for
This is one reason that
Perhaps the most important inequality associated with
If
This includes the formal case where
This condition on
Here we might think of
From this, one might ask if we actually have equality above. If you’re feeling
particularly optimistic, you might even wonder if we can characterize which
functionals in
Now for the magic part:
For
where
When
The proof of this fact actually goes through complex valued measures!
If
Notice this means that for
so
Frequently one has a function
For instance, when doing fourier analysis, our hilbert space techniques only
work for
With that said, here are the main theorems for useful inclusions:
If
Formally, if
(As an easy exercise, you should prove this)
If
Formally, if
(Again, this is a fairly easy exercise)
In fact, both of the above statements are equivalences.
So going down is allowed if and only if
Notice how these line up with the singularity/rapid decay tradeoff we
mentioned earlier. If
Conversely, if there are sets of minimal measure, then (intuitively) any singularity on one of your atoms can’t be avoided, and we get the inclusion of “rapidly decaying” functions into “slowly decaying” functions with no further qualifications15.
Of course, once we know that, say
It turns out that
We also have interpolation functions which, if
If
That is, every
If
That is, the
In fact, we have the bound
for
Alright, that was another huge information dump! This post felt less like a
motivated tour through
I’ve learned from my mistakes, and I’m not going to try and give a concrete date for the next post. All I’ll say is: See you soon ^_^
-
I’ve been busier than expected… So much for one post a day, haha. ↩
-
The notation comes from a (non-obvious) theorem that
-
This is one pressing reason to quotient by almost-everywhere equivalence. Do you see why
would not be a norm if we didn’t identify equivalent functions?One reasonable question might be whether we can always find a canonical representative for a given equivalence class modulo nullsets. That is, given a “function” in
(which is really an equivalence class of functions) can we select an honest-to-goodness function from each class? Obviously the axiom of choice trivializes this, but we would like to do so in a way that’s actually implementable.This is an extremely interesting question, and is the fundamental question in lifting theory. ↩
-
Don’t worry – we’ll be talking a lot about banach spaces in an upcoming post. But
spaces are very fundamental examples, so it’s worth talking about them first. ↩ -
We’ll talk about Fourier theory in an upcoming post too! ↩
-
Recall we define the lebesgue integral of
to be the limit of the integrals of simple functions below . ↩ -
This is in line with an apocryphal quote of Grothendieck (which is probably not actually his) that it’s better to have good categories with bad objects, than bad categories with good objects.
That is, we want our categories to have all limits, colimits, exponentials, etc. even if it means introducing “pathological” objects. It’s easier to know you can take limits and worry about what the result looks like later than it is to constantly worry about whether you can take the limit at all.
Similarly, from an analytic lens, it’s better to have a complete space (which admits potentially ugly functions) than it is to have an incomplete space in which every function is nice. ↩
-
You need boundedness in order to guarantee that the sup norm
is finitely valued. ↩ -
Actually, we can get by with slightly less.
We always have a natural map
which sends to the functional .It turns out this map is an isometric embedding if and only if
is semifinite. That is, when any infinite measure set contains a set of finite measure. This is obviously a super mild assumption.Moreover, this map is surjective (and thus an isometry) when
is “localizable”. See here, for instance. ↩ -
embeds isometrically inside , but in this is not surjective.To build a functional on
that doesn’t come from some function, we look at the subspace of continuous functions, and consider evaluation at a point. We can extend this functional to the whole space via the Hahn-Banach Theorem, and it’s pretty quick to see that this can’t come from an function (since a dirac delta function doesn’t really exist).We’ll talk more about the Hahn-Banach theorem in a future post, but importantly it relies on the axiom of choice! There are actually models of set theory where Hahn-Banach fails, and which think that
really is ! See Martin Väth’s The Dual Space of is , as well as the excellent discussion here ↩ -
The question of which
-modules are reflexive has also been asked. It’s a more subtle question, but finitely generated projective modules always have this property.As an aside that I can’t help but mention, apparently there is a banach space which is isomorphic to its double dual, but for which the canonical evaluation map is not the isomorphism! It’s called James’s Space, for the interested. ↩
-
For instance, an integral that takes values in a banach space might not satisfy the radon-nikodym theorem. If your banach space is reflexive, though, then it does. This came from the linked mse question, so I might be misquoting the result or dropping some hypotheses, but this already makes the notion of reflexivity seem more interesting. ↩
-
For proofs of these exercises, and indeed proofs of the stronger equivalences, see here ↩
-
This may require some meditation.
The idea is that we don’t care if a function is singular as long as the infinity can be contained to a set of small enough measure. But if there are no sets of “small enough” measure, then any singularity is bad. ↩
-
In the motivational section before this, we mention that
. Now we see why: has no (nonnull) sets of measure . ↩ -
In the sense that meagre sets and nullsets both form
-ideals. Note, however, that they are very different notions of “small”, and a set which is small in one sense need not be small in the other.For instance, fat cantor sets can have arbitrarily large measure (in particular, they are not null) yet they are always meagre. ↩